Поиск по сайту




Пишите нам: info@ethology.ru

Follow etholog on Twitter

Система Orphus

Новости
Библиотека
Видео
Разное
Кросс-культурный метод
Старые форумы
Рекомендуем
Не в тему

список статей


Punishing free riders: direct and indirect promotion of cooperation

Mizuho Shinadaab, Toshio Yamagishia

1. Introduction

2. Study 1

2.1. Methods

2.2. Results

3. Study 2

3.1. Methods

3.2. Results

3.2.1. Cooperation

3.2.2. Punishments delivered

3.2.3. Other findings

4. Discussion

Acknowledgment

References

Copyright

1. Introduction

One of the most distinguishing features of human societies is large-scale cooperation among nonkin. Examples of such cooperation include hunting, meat sharing, and collaborative childcare in hunter–gatherer societies; contributions to public goods, such as an irrigation system in agriculturalist societies; and market exchanges in industrialized societies. Cooperation produces mutually beneficial outcomes yet is costly for an individual. Some cooperative behavior can be understood by kin selection (Hamilton, 1964)—helping others can enhance a benefactor's inclusive fitness when the beneficiary is a genetic relative—and by direct reciprocity between those who are willing to trade off the roles of benefactor and beneficiary (Trivers, 1971). These two mechanisms can account for much of the cooperative behavior observed among animals, including humans, but are insufficient to explain costly cooperation in sizeable human groups consisting of genetically unrelated individuals in the absence of long-term relationships. While free riding on a public good is expected from kin-based and reciprocal altruism under these circumstances, experimental studies have shown nontrivial contributions in anonymously played one-shot games with genetically unrelated participants (Andreoni & Petrie, 2004, Issac & Walker, 1988, Marwell & Ames, 1979, Orbell et al., 1988, Rapoport, 1987, Yamagishi, 1988).

One possible explanation for cooperation in human groups is the punishment of free riders. Experimental studies have consistently demonstrated that punishment (monetary and symbolic alike) promotes cooperation (Fehr & Fischbacher, 2003, Fehr & Gächter, 2002, Masclet et al., 2003). Not only do people show a propensity to cooperate under the threat of punishment in experimental games, they are also willing to absorb costs for administering punishment to free riders (Anderson & Putterman, 2006, Casari & Plott, 2003, Price et al., 2002). Given the power of punishment to promote cooperation, it is surprising to us that many theorists have generally overlooked the reason for punishment's efficacy. We speculate that the paucity of effort to address this question is at least partly based on the fact that the answer seems self-evident; administration of punishment transforms outcomes of cooperation and defection such that cooperation is more profitable than free riding. This direct effect of punishment could be the sole factor in explaining cooperation if, and only if, one assumes that humans are strictly self-regarding with no consideration for consequences to others. Olson (1965) clearly follows this logic when he wrote “… rational, self-interested individuals will not act to achieve their common or group interests” (p. 2) and “only a separate and selective incentive will stimulate a rational individual in a latent group to act in a group-oriented way” (p. 51).

In this paper, we argue that direct effect (the transformation of incentives for potential targets of punishment) alone is limited in its ability to explain the robust effect of punishment. The limitation arises from the fact that punishment incurs cost to the punisher, whereas the benefit of punishment (public welfare generated by greater cooperation) is shared equally by all members. Thus, the provision of punishment involves a free-rider problem in itself; self-regarding individuals should not pay the cost associated with imposing penalties on free riders. This problem is called second-order public good dilemma (Oliver, 1980). Faced with this difficulty, some researchers have argued that the cost of punishment becomes smaller in higher-order public good dilemmas (e.g., punishment of nonpunishers, punishment of those who do not punish nonpunishers, etc.) than in the original public good dilemma (Boyd et al., 2003, Boyd & Richerson, 1992, Henrich, 2004, Henrich & Boyd, 2001, Sober & Wilson, 1998). Once the cost is reduced sufficiently for the provision of punishment at a higher level, it should eventually stabilize cooperation in the original public good dilemma.

We claim below that this cost-reduction argument can be augmented by an efficiency-enhancement argument. In addition to the possibility that the cost associated with providing punishment is smaller than that associated with providing the original public good, we suggest that an indirect effect of punishment further enhances the efficiency of punishment. There is a robust finding that an overwhelming majority of players in the public goods game behave as conditional cooperators (individuals who cooperate if, and only if, other members cooperate) rather than as unconditional cooperators or unconditional defectors (Andreoni & Miller, 1993, Boehm, 1999, Kurzban & Houser, 2005, Page et al., 2005). Although players almost always defect in response to defection in a public goods game, the majority of players choose to cooperate when other players cooperate (Cho & Choi, 2000, Clark & Sefton, 2001, Fischbacher et al., 2001, Hayashi et al., 1999, Kiyonari et al., 2000, Watabe et al., 1996). Moreover, numerous studies have demonstrated a relationship between expectation of cooperation and cooperative behavior; the stronger is the expectation that others will cooperate, the more likely it is that a player will choose to cooperate (Charness & Dufwenberg, 2006, Dawes, 1980, Pruitt & Kimmel, 1977). Conditional cooperators seek mutually beneficial opportunities, but only when their effort is unlikely to be exploited by free riders. For them, the expectation that others will cooperate is a necessary (although not sufficient) antecedent to a cooperative venture. The threat of punishment for free riding provides reassurance to conditional cooperators that other group members will also cooperate. This reassurance that others will also cooperate satisfies their condition for cooperation. Punishment promotes cooperation among conditional cooperators through the reassurance it provides, rather than by the fear of being a target of penalization (the direct effect of punishment). We call this the indirect effect of punishment.

Most experimental studies of punishment (e.g., Fehr & Gächter, 2002, Ostrom et al., 1992, Yamagishi, 1986) do not appreciate the possibility that indirect effect supplements the direct effect of punishment and, instead, analyze the combined effect (including both direct and indirect effects) of punishment for promoting cooperation. The purpose of this study is to demonstrate the augmentative nature of the indirect effect, such that the combined effect of punishment is greater than the level expected from the direct effect alone. For this purpose, we compare the size of punishment's combined effect with the size of the direct effect alone. Specifically, we design a one-shot three-person prisoner's dilemma (PD) game with three between-subjects conditions: no-punishment condition, direct-effect (of punishment) condition, and combined-effect (of punishment) condition. We adopt a one-shot, rather than a repeated-game, design often used in the study of punishment (Anderson & Putterman, 2006, Fehr & Gächter, 2002, Ostrom et al., 1992, Yamagishi, 1986). The reason for the use of a one-shot game instead of a repeated game is that measurement of the direct effect, in its pure form free from contaminating influences of indirect effects, is an indispensable part of this study. In repeated games, those who are afraid of receiving a penalty (i.e., those who experience the direct effect of punishment) and thus cooperate at a higher level may unwittingly promote the cooperation of other players who are conditional cooperators. The improved level of cooperation of the other players might, in turn, improve the original players' level of cooperation. That is, the direct effect of punishment in repeated games can engender an indirect effect through the other players' behavior; thus, identifying the direct effect of punishment in its pure form is theoretically impossible. This difficulty of identifying the direct effect can be avoided in one-shot games in which changes in one player's behavior are not reflected in the other players' behavior. On the other hand, whether or not punishment has an effect in the absence of the actual experience of being punished has been debated, and no firm conclusions have yet been reached (Eek et al., 2002, Loukopoulos et al., 2006, Walker & Halloran, 2004). The current study thus aspires, first, to provide evidence for the effect of punishment in the absence of the actual experience of punishment, and, second, to sort out the indirect and direct effects of punishment from their combined effect.

We conducted two experiments, with the major difference between the two residing in the punishment mechanism. In the first study, punishment was provided exogenously. That is, penalties were imposed by the experimenter, requiring no cost to be paid by players themselves. In contrast, punishment in Study 2 was endogenous, dispensed by individual game players themselves who had to pay a cost for its provision. In both experiments, each player of a three-person PD game first decided what portion of an initial endowment one would contribute to benefit the other two players. Afterwards, players faced the possibility of punishment for free riding. In the direct-effect condition, the participant alone faced the possibility of punishment. Since no penalties were administered to the other players, they could free ride with impunity. Thus, only the direct effect of punishment could influence the participant's decision to cooperate. In the combined-effect condition, all players were subject to punishment. Thus, in addition to the direct effect of punishment for free riding, participants could expect greater cooperation (on average) from their fellow group members who also faced the possibility of penalization. In the no-punishment condition, there was no penalty for free riding. Thus, any difference in the sum contributed between the direct-effect condition and the no-punishment condition must be due to the direct effect of punishment alone. In this sense, any additional contribution in the combined-effect condition, over and above that observed in the direct-effect condition, can be regarded as evidence for the indirect effect.

2. Study 1

2.1. Methods

A total of 157 freshmen (79 men and 78 women) at Hokkaido University in Japan participated in this experiment for monetary rewards. They were recruited from a large subject pool consisting of freshmen from various disciplines and were randomly assigned to one of three conditions (52 in the no-punishment condition, 51 in the direct-effect condition, and 54 in the combined-effect condition). Two of the participants misunderstood the instructions and were removed from the analysis.1 Participants were assured that their contributions would remain anonymous to both the other participants and to the experimenter with whom they met in person.

In all three conditions, participants played a one-shot three-person PD game. Participants were escorted to individual rooms without seeing or talking to other participants. Each member of the three-person group was provided with an endowment of ¥800 from the experimenter and was asked to contribute some portion of that endowment to the other group members. The actual amount was left up to each player. Each player received the total amount contributed by the other two players. Thus, if everybody contributed the full endowment of ¥800, each player received ¥1600 (¥800 from each of the other players). Since each player decided on the sum to contribute without knowing the value of the other contributions, contributing nothing was the most profitable choice regardless of the amount other members decided to contribute. In the event that all three players adopted this strategy of contributing nothing, each would retain one's original endowment of ¥800. Thus, the monetary payoff for each participant i in the no-punishment condition is given by

(1)
where y is the endowment and a is the benefit generated by another member's cooperation (y=800 and a=1; note that the participant's own contribution does not generate any benefit to oneself, as implied by ji).

Players in the no-punishment condition neither faced punishment nor were informed that punishment was even a possibility. Conversely, players in the remaining two conditions were informed that they might be punished if they did not contribute the entire sum of their endowment to the other group members. Furthermore, players in the two punishment conditions were informed that there was an increasing probability of punishment as the value of their contribution decreased; however, players were not told of specific probabilities.2 We chose to implement a punishment mechanism with incomplete information regarding the probability of being punished, since the exact probability of punishment at various levels of cooperation is hardly available in the real world. Punishment was imposed exogenously by the experimenter, although this method of administering punishment was changed in the second study. While we used the term “punishment” in the instructions of the first experiment, we omitted the term in the second study. We discuss the implications of using (or not using) the term “punishment” in the general discussion.

When a player was penalized, one lost half of the portion of the endowment one kept at hand. Thus, the monetary payoff for each participant i when one is punished is given by:

(2)
The monetary payoff for the participant who was not punished is given by Eq. (1).

Participants in the direct-effect condition were further told that only one of the three participants would be subject to punishment and that they had been randomly chosen as the sole target of punishment. They were further instructed that the other players would remain uninformed of this fact, having no knowledge about the possibility of punishment. Since the participant alone was subject to punishment and the other members were not subject to punishment, only the direct effect was possible in this condition. Players in the combined-effect condition were told that all three members of the group would face the possibility of punishment. In order to keep the threat of receiving punishment constant across the two punishment conditions, players were told that the probability of punishment would be determined independently for each player, so that the likelihood of punishment was unaffected by decisions made by other players.

Three players assigned to the combined-effect condition were grouped together to constitute a single group to play a public goods game. Other experimental groups consisted of one player from the direct-effect condition and two players from the no-punishment condition. In order to maintain balance in the number of players assigned to each condition, one player in the no-punishment condition was sometimes paired with more than one player in the direct-effect condition when calculating their rewards.3

After the experiment, all participants completed a postexperimental questionnaire. Finally, they were informed of their game outcome: how much each of the three members contributed, whether or not they received a penalty (in the two punishment conditions), and how much they earned. A secretary who knew nothing about the experiment paid each participant individually and then discharged them. The research protocol was approved by the ethics committee of the Department of Behavioral Science at Hokkaido University.

2.2. Results

Because there were no main or interaction effects involving players' sex, the following analyses used combined data for men and women. The results of the first study (Fig. 1) show that the base rate level of cooperation (the portion of the initial endowment contributed for other members) in the no-punishment condition was ¥239.81 (S.D.=197.03) or about 30% of the endowment. Cooperation levels in the two punishment conditions were higher than thisbase rate level (direct-effect condition: ¥345.60, S.D.=223.80; combined-effect condition: ¥435.47, S.D.=231.17). We conducted a set of regression analyses for cooperation level using two dummy variables: one for the presence of punishment (Dummy 1; zero in the no-punishment condition and one in the direct-effect and combined-effect conditions) and the other for the presence of indirect effect (Dummy 2; zero in the no-punishment and direct-effect conditions and one in the combined-effect condition). Column 1 in Table 1 includes only Dummy 1; the effect for the dummy variable represents the difference in cooperation level between the no-punishment condition and the two punishment conditions combined. The significant regression effect for this variable in Column 1 shows that punishment increased the cooperation level by ¥152.04.


View full-size image.

Fig. 1. Direct and indirect effects of punishment in the first study. The left bar estimates the base level of cooperation (sum of contribution) that occurs when free riding is not punished. The darker portion of the middle bar (¥105.79) represents the direct effect of punishment—cooperation over and above that observed in the no-punishment condition. The right bar illustrates the combined effect of punishment (direct and indirect) on cooperation; the darker portion (¥89.87) represents the contribution level over and above that observed for the direct effect of punishment (i.e., the indirect effect of punishment). Error bars represent standard error.


Table 1.

The effects of anticipated punishment on cooperation in Study 1

Variables 1 2
Dummy 1 152.04 (37.47), p<.0001 105.79 (43.15), p=.015
Dummy 2 89.87 (42.95), p=.038
Constant 239.81 (30.54), p<.0001 239.81 (30.21), p<.0001
n 155 155
R2 .10 .12

Regression analyses for contribution level on two dummy variables.

Standard errors are presented in parentheses.

The second dummy was then added to the regression equation (Column 2) to decompose the overall effect of punishment into two components: one for the direct effect and one for the indirect effect. The contribution level in the no-punishment condition is represented by the constant in Column 2, since both dummies are zero in this condition. The contribution level in the direct-effect condition is the sum of the constant and the regression coefficient for Dummy 1 (that takes the value of one); thus, the coefficient for Dummy 1 represents the difference in cooperation between the no-punishment condition and the direct-effect condition. In Fig. 1, this effect corresponds to the dark portion of the bar for the direct-effect condition. Similarly, the coefficient for Dummy 2 represents the difference in cooperation between the direct-effect condition and the combined-effect condition, corresponding to the dark portion of the bar for the combined-effect condition. The two effects are similar in size, indicating that the indirect effect was almost as strong as the direct effect. The interpretation of the relative sizes of these two effects, however, has to be made with caution, since effect sizes depend on the parameters used in the experiment, including the cost and benefit for cooperation and the cost and size of punishment.

We expected that participants would cooperate more in the combined-effect condition than in the direct-effect condition, since the expectation that other members would cooperate due to possible punishment would be higher in the former condition than in the latter. We also argued that since there was no possibility that other members would be punished in the no-punishment and direct-effect conditions, participants' expectations would not differ between the two. We measured participants' expectations in the postexperimental questionnaire by asking, “How much do you think the other two contributed on average?” The average expectation was ¥400.57 (S.D.=129.12) in the combined-effect condition, ¥329.00 (S.D.=130.58) in the direct-effect condition, and ¥274.33 (S.D.=157.81) in the no-punishment condition. A regression analysis using a set of two dummy variables (see analysis of contributions) indicated that both the difference between the direct-effect condition and the combined-effect condition [b=71.57, t(152)=2.60, p=.01] and the difference between the no-punishment condition and the direct-effect condition [b=54.67, t(152)=1.97, p=.05] were significant. While the former difference provides support for our argument, the unanticipated difference between the no-punishment condition and the direct-effect condition strongly suggests that at least a substantial portion of the participants' responses to postexperimental questions represents a “projection” of their own behavior onto the other members. Participants in the direct-effect condition overestimated the other two members' actual contribution (¥329.00 vs. ¥239.81) to match their own contribution (¥345.60), at least in their responses to postexperimental questions, whereas estimations of those in the no-punishment condition (¥274.33 vs. ¥239.81) and in the combined-effect condition (¥400.57 vs. ¥435.47) did not greatly differ from the actual levels of contribution. We do not know whether this overestimation by participants in the direct-effect condition occurred in the experiment and affected their decisions, or emerged only in their responses to the postexperimental question. However, even if it had affected their decision in the experiment, it should have made their contribution higher rather than lower. The “inflated” level of contribution in the direct-effect condition beyond the effect caused by the threat of punishment alone, if existing at all, should have worked against our hypothesis concerning indirect effect. Thus, this result provided stronger support to our conclusion about indirect effect.

3. Study 2

The results of the first study confirmed, first, that the threat of punishment can enhance cooperation in a one-shot PD game. These results further provided evidence that the indirect effect of punishment augments its direct effect. This finding, however, has to be qualified in two important respects. First, the punishment was imposed exogenously by the experimenter, rather than voluntarily administered by players themselves. Second, administration of punishment required no cost from the players. These two features of punishment in the first study are problematic for generalizing the results beyond this particular enforcement mechanism. When players are required to pay a personal cost to impose penalties, the likelihood of punishment of free riding may be less than that expected when the experimenter acts as a requiter. The direct effect of punishment may thus be reduced when the administration of punishment is costly. Consequently, the expectation that other people will cooperate to avoid punishment may also be reduced. As a result, the promotion of cooperation through the indirect effect would be reduced.

We conducted a second study to examine whether the indirect effect of punishment observed in the first study would be replicated under a different enforcement mechanism. In the second study, players decided how much personal cost to bear in order to administer punishment to other players who fail to contribute. In addition, we decided not to use the term “punishment” in the second study. Instead, we chose to use the neutral word “reduce” in order to avoid eliciting normative behavior associated with the term “punishment.”

The use of the endogenous punishment mechanism forced us to give up measuring the pure direct effect of punishment as we did in Study 1. In the first experiment, participants in the direct-effect condition were informed that the other two players were unaware of punishment at all. In Study 2, however, the other two players were aware of the existence of punishment because they were able to deliver punishment to the participant in the direct-effect condition. Participants in the direct condition in the second study thus face players who may be affected by the indirect effect of punishment, since other players face someone (the participant in the direct-effect condition) who can be punished. That is, participants in the direct-effect condition in the second study may be affected by the expectation of indirect effect that may enhance other players' cooperation—we may call this doubly indirect effect of punishment. We decided to run the endogenous punishment mechanism despite the inability to measure the purely direct effect mentioned above, since the merits of the new design outweigh this potential problem. Furthermore, this doubly indirect effect of punishment should work against our hypothesis concerning the operation of indirect effect because the test of indirect effect now involves cooperation in the combined effect and “inflated” (due to the doubly indirect effect) level of cooperation in the direct-effect condition.

3.1. Methods

A total of 144 freshmen (72 men and 72 women) at Hokkaido University in Japan participated in this experiment for monetary rewards. All participants played the same one-shot three-person PD game used in the first study. Each member of a three-person group was asked to contribute some portion of one's endowment of ¥800 for other group members. Each of the other two players received the amount the player contributed.

Participants were randomly assigned to one of three conditions (48 in the no-punishment condition, 48 in the direct-effect condition, and 48 in the combined-effect condition). Three of the participants were removed from the analysis because their responses to postexperimental questions made it clear that they failed to comprehend the instructions.4 The use of an endogenous punishment system forced us to use “extra” participants to avoid deception. Participants in the direct-effect condition were the only potential targets of punishment in their group. The other two participants in their group did not face the possibility of receiving punishment. They were informed that a punishment option existed in their group. Furthermore, one of the two was given a chance to punish another player (the participant in the direct-effect condition). These features disqualified them as players in the no-punishment condition. We did not use these “extra” participants in our hypothesis testing, since they were not relevant to our hypotheses.

Players in the no-punishment condition constituted a group in which no one faced punishment. The monetary payoff for each participant in the no-punishment condition is given by Eq. (1). Players in the remaining two conditions were informed that they might be punished by other players. We introduced a system of punishment in which one participant could be punished only by one other participant in order to make punishment compatible across the two punishment conditions. If we allowed both of the other two participants to punish the participant in the direct-effect condition, he or she would be subject to punishment by two individuals. In contrast, no participant in the combined-effect condition was the sole target of punishment by two individuals simultaneously, since each of the other two participants had two potential targets to choose from. As a result, participants in the direct-effect condition faced twice as strong a punishment as those in the indirect-effect condition. This problem was avoided by restricting the number of potential punishers in the direct-effect condition to one. Remember that the group for the direct-effect condition included the potential target of punishment D1 and two “extra” participants; one of the two (DE1) was given an opportunity to punish D1, whereas the other (DE2) did not have such an opportunity. Only the sole target of punishment in this group D1 qualified for the direct-effect condition; the other two “extra” participants were included in this group to avoid deceiving the participants.

The monetary payoff for player D1 in the direct-effect condition is given by

(3)
where p is the amount of money that DE1 pays to punish D1. Player D1 in the direct-effect condition may be punished only by DE1. Since D1 did not have an opportunity to punish another player, Eq. (3) does not include the cost of punishment.

Participant C1 in the combined-effect condition was a target of potential punishment by C2; C2 in the combined-effect condition was a target of potential punishment by C3; and C3 in the combined-effect condition was a target of potential punishment by C1. Therefore, the monetary payoff for each participant in the combined-effect condition is given by

(4)
where ji, ik, kj, and pik is the amount of money that group member i pays to punish group member k.

After all participants had decided how much to contribute to the three-person PD game, each participant in the combined-effect condition (and extra participants in the direct-effect condition) was informed of how much the target of one's punishment contributed. Then, they were given an opportunity to reduce the earnings of that member. They were told that monetary costs were required to use the option; each yen the participant paid reduced the target member's earnings by ¥2. The maximum amount they could pay to reduce another's earnings was ¥200—the amount they were paid before the experiment as a show-up fee (in addition to the endowment of ¥800 given them during the experiment). After deciding how much to pay to reduce the earnings of that member, all participants completed a postexperimental questionnaire. Finally, they were informed of how much they earned in the PD game and, if they were subjected to punishment, by how much their earnings were reduced. Finally, participants were paid their earnings individually (less the penalty) and dismissed.

3.2. Results

We found no main or interaction effects involving the sex of the participants; therefore, data were pooled across sexes for all subsequent analyses.

3.2.1. Cooperation

As shown in Fig. 2, the results of the second study largely replicated those of the first study. On average, the contribution level was lowest (¥237.71, S.D.=264.56) in the no-punishment condition, highest (¥414.13, S.D.=256.13) in the combined-effect condition, and intermediate in the direct-effect condition (¥323.62, S.D.=240.95). We used the same set of regression analyses used in Study 1 to examine, first, whether punishment had a positive overall effect on cooperation and, second, whether the predicted indirect effect manifested. Column 1 in Table 2 includes only Dummy 1. The significant effect for this dummy variable in Column 1 represents the difference in cooperation level between the no-punishment condition and the two punishment conditions combined. As was the case with exogenous punishment, the results of Study 2 clearly show that endogenous punishment can increase cooperation level even in a one-shot game. The dummy variable for the indirect effect was then added to the regression equation (Column 2) to decompose the combined effect of punishment into two components: direct and indirect effects. In Column 2, either Dummy 1, representing the direct effect (the dark portion of the bar in Fig. 2 for the direct-effect condition), or Dummy 2, representing the indirect effect (the dark portion of the bar for the combined-effect condition), reached statistical significance at α=.05. These results demonstrate, first, that punishment has a positive effect on contribution, and, second, that the positive effect of punishment can be decomposed into direct and indirect effects of roughly equivalence sizes, although each of the effects was not as strong as in the first study.


View full-size image.

Fig. 2. Direct and indirect effects of punishment on the second study. The left bar estimates the base level of cooperation (sum of contribution) that occurs when free riding is not punished. The darker portion of the middle bar (¥85.91) represents the direct effect of punishment—cooperation over and above that observed in the no-punishment condition. The right bar illustrates the combined effect of punishment (direct and indirect) on cooperation; the darker portion (¥90.73) represents the contribution level over and above that observed for the direct effect of punishment (i.e., the indirect effect of punishment). Error bars represent standard error.


Table 2.

The effects of anticipated punishment on cooperation in Study 2

Variables 1 2
Dummy 1 130.79 (45.48), p=.005 85.91 (52.15), p=.102
Dummy 2 90.73 (52.71), p=.087
Constant 237.71 (36.94), p<.0001 237.71 (36.68), p<.0001
n 141 141
R2 .06 .08

Regression analyses for contribution level on two dummy variables.

Standard errors are presented in parentheses.

Expectations of other players' contributions were also similar to the pattern observed in the first study. We measured participants' expectations using the same postexperimental question used in the first study. The average expectation was ¥370.65 (S.D.=182.75) in the combined-effect condition, ¥286.17 (S.D.=172.17) in the direct-effect condition, and ¥236.04 (S.D.=177.89) in the no-punishment condition. A regression analysis using a set of two dummy variables (see analysis of contributions) indicated that the difference between the direct-effect condition and the combined-effect condition was significant [b=84.48, t(138)=2.29, p=.02], whereas the difference between the no-punishment condition and the direct-effect condition [b=50.13, t(138)=1.38, p=.17] was not significant.

3.2.2. Punishments delivered

Enforcement of punishment by participants was relatively sparse, possibly because of the relatively high contribution levels of players who were subjected to the threat of penalization or perhaps because punishment was costly. Only 26% of the participants in the combined-effect condition (12 of 46 participants) delivered some level of punishment. Those who punished spent an average of ¥87.5 (S.D.=62.25) to reduce another's earnings. As in previous studies (Fehr & Gächter, 2002, Falk et al., 2005), punishment was more severe when the target's contribution level was less than the punisher's. In this case, an average of ¥105.71 (S.D.=71.61) was spent on penalties to 39% of potential targets. When the target of punishment contributed more than the punisher, an average of ¥62.00 (S.D.=39.62) was spent on penalties to 18% of potential targets.5 The total cost of punishment (i.e., the amount participants spent on punishment) was relatively small, compared to the benefit of increased cooperation. On average, each participant contributed ¥176.64 more in the combined-effect condition than in the no-punishment condition. This extra contribution generated a benefit of 176.64×2=¥353.28 for the other two members. That is, each participant generated a net benefit of ¥176.64 (¥353.28 of total benefits for the cost of ¥176.64) while spending an average of ¥22.83 on punishment. Since punishment reduced the earnings of the target by ¥45.66, each participant in the combined-effect condition was better off, on average, than those in the no-punishment condition by 176.64−22.83−45.66=¥108.15. In the direct-effect condition, the participant's average contribution level was higher than that in the no-punishment condition by 85.91, thus producing an extra net benefit of ¥85.91. The matched extra participant spent an average of ¥22.34 for punishment. Thus, the overall benefit of punishment in the direct-effect condition was ¥18.89. Supplementing the direct effect with the indirect effect thus made the administration of punishment much more cost-effective.

3.2.3. Other findings

“Extra” participants (DE1 and DE2) were used to avoid the use of deception. They did not face the threat of punishment, yet they knew that one of the three players would possibly face punishment. Thus, their contributions may possibly be influenced by the indirect effect of punishment. On the other hand, they were also aware that two of the three players were exempt from punishment. This would make the indirect effect much weaker than the one observed in the combined-effect condition in which all three members faced possible punishment. Their responses to the postexperimental question concerning the expectations of the other players' contributions suggest that their average expectations were higher than those in the no-punishment condition (¥236.04). One of the two “extra” participants, the one who was given a chance to deliver punishment (DE1), expected that the other two would contribute an average of ¥326.46 (S.D.=206.40), while the other “extra” participant (DE2), who was neither punished nor given an opportunity for punishment, expected ¥313.89 (S.D.=126.96). Despite these heightened expectations, their contributions were not larger (¥270.00, S.D.=294.39 for DE1; ¥198.33, S.D.=232.49 for DE2) than in the no-punishment condition (¥237.71). There results indicate the lack of an indirect effect among those participants. We discuss the implications of this finding in the Discussion section.

4. Discussion

The results of the two experiments support our argument that the direct effect of punishment is augmented by an indirect effect to enhance cooperation. This is evident in the fact that the level of cooperation in the combined-effect condition was greater than that observed in either the no-punishment condition or the direct-effect punishment condition.

As described earlier, the indirect effect of punishment has long been overlooked despite its importance in solving the second-order dilemma. Eek et al. (2002) and Loukopoulos et al. (2006) are among the few who recognized the importance of the indirect effect—which they called the “spillover effect”—of punishment. They found evidence of an indirect effect of punishment, but the indirect effect was observed in their study only when the direct effect of punishment exogenously imposed by the experimenter was strong enough to make cooperation a more profitable choice than free riding (i.e., when the size of the imposed penalty exceeds the cost of cooperation). In this case, participants in their experiments cooperated at a higher level when one of the other members of a five-person group was under the threat of such strong punishment than when no penalties were administered. However, their studies failed to demonstrate that the direct effect of weak punishment (i.e., not strong enough to make cooperation a more profitable choice than free riding) is augmented by an indirect effect. The current study is the first to demonstrate that the direct effect of weak punishment, which by itself is not strong enough to make self-regarding people cooperate, is augmented by an indirect effect.

Our success in demonstrating an indirect effect of punishment when the penalty was less than the cost of cooperation suggests that the symbolic or social nature of punishment (Blau, 1964, Masclet et al., 2003, Noussair & Tucker, 2005) may play an important role in producing indirect effects. In Study 1, we explicitly used the term “punishment,” whereas Eek et al. (2002) expressed their penalty as a “fee of 1000 SEK for [choosing noncooperation]” (p. 809). When participants encountered the term “punishment” in the instructions in our first study, they may have taken note of the social implications of being a target of punishment, in addition to the monetary cost imposed by the punishment itself. Recognition of the social implications of punishment then may have made them more aware of social norms and obligations for cooperation, and of the fact that others also operate under the normative pressure for cooperation. This could, in turn, have strengthened the indirect effect of punishment. This seems to be a reasonable account for the difference between our findings in the first study and those reported by Eek et al. However, we replicated the same effects in the second study in which the term “punishment” was not used. The use of the term “punishment,” thus, is not a necessary condition for the indirect effect of punishment. On the other hand, there is a further possibility that the social implications of punishment may have played an important role in enhancing the indirect effect. It is possible that the interpersonal nature of endogenous punishment used in Study 2 made the social nature of punishment (i.e., the fact that punishment is something others would want to enforce) salient to the participants. Whether or not the social aspects of punishment are necessary for the indirect effect of “weak” punishment is an important topic for future studies.

Another topic for future studies is the lack of indirect effects observed among the “extra” participants in the second study. We used these participants mainly to avoid the use of deception in the direct-effect condition. That is, one of the two “extra” participants DE1 punished the “real” participant D1 in the direct-effect condition, while he or she was not subject to punishment. Another “extra” participant DE2 knew that DE1 could punish D1. In short, they knew that one of the other two players was subject to punishment and, thus, would possibly improve his or her cooperation level. This might produce an indirect effect. On the other hand, the presence of another player who was immune from punishment might have discouraged cooperation. Given the finding by Kurzban, McCabe, Smith, and Wilson (2001) that conditional cooperators are sensitive to the presence of noncooperators, the presence of the immune player is likely to prevent the indirect effect of punishment from taking place. Another possible explanation for the lack of an indirect effect among these “extra” participants is that the indirect effect of punishment augments the weak direct effect of punishment, rather than taking place by itself in the absence of a direct effect. That is, the nature of the indirect effect is supplementary. Whether the indirect effect of punishment emerges by itself or requires the presence of a direct effect is an important topic for future studies.

The indirect effect of punishment was suggested originally by Hobbes (1651) in the 17th century. It is a popular misconception that Hobbes was an advocate of the central authority forcing unwilling subjects to disarm (i.e., to use the direct effect of punishment to force people to cooperate) (Kavka, 1983, Taylor, 1976, Yamagishi, 1992). Instead, his argument was focused more on the indirect effect of punishment: the Leviathan (the central authority) playing the role of reducing fear of exploitation among those who prefer peace to war such that they can safely disarm themselves (i.e., cooperate) without fear of being exploited by those who do not. The current study is the first study to demonstrate experimentally the importance of the indirect effect as implied by the view of Hobbes on Leviathan; punishment is a guarantor of peace, not (strictly) its enforcer. We have confirmed experimentally that the boost to cooperation commonly observed in studies of punishment is better understood as a consequence of two separate influences: one altering payoffs associated with cooperation and defection (the direct effect) and the other enhancing the expectation of cooperation by others (the indirect effect).

The role of the indirect effect of punishment is argued to play a particularly important role in the maintenance of common pool resources through voluntary establishment of social institutions that monitor and sanction their members. Researchers of resource management have alluded to the complementary nature of direct and indirect effects in field studies of common resources (Dietz, Ostrom, & Stern, 2003); while not ruling out the importance of the direct effect of punishment, they have argued that “ruling by the sword” alone is insufficient to convince people to behave in a mutually beneficial manner (Bewley, 1999, Gardner et al., 1990, Ostrom et al., 1992). This is because the key to a successful sanctioning system is the consent of the people under its regulation (Hardin, 1968); voluntary acceptance assures that those who are regulated want to cooperate, thereby enhancing the efficacy of punishment with the indirect effect. We further suspect that factors such as ideology and shared beliefs also play a positive role in raising expectations that others act cooperatively and, consequently, accentuate the power of the indirect effect. The efficacy-enhancing role of the indirect effect should be pronounced in social institutions perceived to be strong and legitimate. While the direct effect depends more on the actual controlling power of a social institution, the indirect effect depends more on the conviction that other members believe in the legitimacy and efficacy of punishment. A sanctioning system supported by a shared belief system should, thus, be more effective than the same system dependent on the “sword” alone. An efficacious sanctioning system supported by beliefs about its legitimacy would function well to induce people to comply, transforming beliefs into reality; such a system could be self-sustaining (Aoki, 2001).

Acknowledgments

We thank Paul Wehr and Mark Radford for their comments on earlier versions of this manuscript, Mai Kasahara for her help in running the experiment, and our colleagues at Hokkaido University for letting us recruit potential participants from their classes.

References

Aoki, 2001 1.Aoki M. Toward a comparative institutional analysis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 2001;.

Anderson & Putterman, 2006 2.Anderson CM, Putterman L. Do non-strategic sanctions obey the law of demand? The demand for punishment in the voluntary contribution mechanism. Games and Economic Behavior. 2006;54:1–24.

Andreoni & Miller, 1993 3.Andreoni J, Miller JH. Rational cooperation in the finitely repeated prisoner's dilemma: Experimental evidence. Economic Journal. 1993;103:570–585.

Andreoni & Petrie, 2004 4.Andreoni J, Petrie R. Public goods experiments without confidentiality: A glimpse into fund-raising. Journal of Public Economics. 2004;88:1605–1623.

Bewley, 1999 5.Bewley T. Why wages don't fall in a recession. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1999;.

Blau, 1964 6.Blau PM. Exchange and power in social life. New York: John Wiley & Sons; 1964;.

Boehm, 1999 7.Boehm C. Hierarchy in the forest: The evolution of egalitarian behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1999;.

Boyd et al., 2003 8.Boyd R, Gintis H, Bowles S, Richerson PJ. The evolution of altruistic punishment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 2003;100:3531–3535. MEDLINE | CrossRef

Boyd & Richerson, 1992 9.Boyd R, Richerson PJ. Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizable groups. Ethology and Sociobiology,. 1992;13:171–195.

Casari & Plott, 2003 10.Casari M, Plott CR. Decentralized management of common property resources: Experiments with a centuries-old institution. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization,. 2003;51:217–247.

Charness & Dufwenberg, 2006 11.Charness G, Dufwenberg M. Promises and partnership. Econometrica,. 2006;74:1579–1601.

Cho & Choi, 2000 12.Cho K, Choi B. A cross-society study of trust and reciprocity: Korea, Japan, and the US. International Studies Review,. 2000;3:31–43.

Clark & Sefton, 2001 13.Clark K, Sefton M. The sequential prisoner's dilemma: Evidence on reciprocation. Economic Journal,. 2001;111:51–68.

Dawes, 1980 14.Dawes RM. Social dilemmas. Annual Review of Psychology,. 1980;31:169–193.

Dietz et al., 2003 15.Dietz T, Ostrom E, Stern PC. The struggle to govern the commons. Science,. 2003;302:1907–1912. CrossRef

Eek et al., 2002 16.Eek D, Loukopoulos P, Fujii S, Garling T. Spill-over effects of intermittent costs for defection in social dilemmas. European Journal of Social Psychology,. 2002;32:801–813.

Falk et al., 2005 17.Falk A, Fehr E, Fischbacher U. Driving forces of informal sanctions. Econometrica,. 2005;73:2017–2030.

Fehr & Fischbacher, 2003 18.Fehr E, Fischbacher U. The nature of human altruism—Proximate patterns and evolutionary origins. Nature,. 2003;425:785–791. CrossRef

Fehr & Gächter, 2002 19.Fehr E, Gächter S. Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature,. 2002;415:137–140. MEDLINE | CrossRef

Fischbacher et al., 2001 20.Fischbacher U, Gächter S, Fehr E. Are people conditionally cooperative? Evidence from a public goods experiment. Economics Letters,. 2001;71:397–404.

Gardner et al., 1990 21.Gardner R, Ostrom E, Walker J. The nature of common-pool resource problems. Rationality and Society,. 1990;2:335–358.

Hamilton, 1964 22.Hamilton WD. The genetical evolution of social behaviour I. Journal of Theoretical Biology,. 1964;7:1–52. MEDLINE | CrossRef

Hardin, 1968 23.Hardin G. The tragedy of the commons. Science. 1968;162:1243–1248. MEDLINE | CrossRef

Hayashi et al., 1999 24.Hayashi N, Ostrom E, Walker J, Yamagishi T. Reciprocity, trust, and the sense of control: A cross-societal study. Rationality and Society,. 1999;11:27–46.

Henrich, 2004 25.Henrich J. Cultural group selection, coevolutionary processes and large-scale cooperation. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization,. 2004;53:3–35.

Henrich & Boyd, 2001 26.Henrich J, Boyd R. Why people punish defectors: Weak conformist transmission can stabilize costly enforcement of norms in cooperative dilemmas. Journal of Theoretical Biology. 2001;208:79–89. MEDLINE | CrossRef

Hobbes, 1651 27.Hobbes T. Leviathan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 1651;.

Issac & Walker, 1988 28.Issac RM, Walker JM. Group size effects in public goods provision: The voluntary contributions mechanism. Quarterly Journal of Economics,. 1988;103:179–199.

Kavka, 1983 29.Kavka GS. Hobbes's war all against all. Ethics,. 1983;93:291–310. CrossRef

Kiyonari et al., 2000 30.Kiyonari T, Tanida S, Yamagishi T. Social exchange and reciprocity: Confusion or a heuristic?. Evolution and Human Behavior,. 2000;21:411–427.

Kurzban & Houser, 2005 31.Kurzban R, Houser D. Experiments investigating cooperative types in humans: A complement to evolutionary theory and simulations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America,. 2005;102:1803–1807. MEDLINE | CrossRef

Kurzban et al., 2001 32.Kurzban R, McCabe K, Smith VL, Wilson BJ. Incremental commitment and reciprocity in a real time public goods game. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,. 2001;27:1662–1673. CrossRef

Loukopoulos et al., 2006 33.Loukopoulos P, Eek D, Garling T, Fujii S. Palatable punishment in real-world social dilemmas?. Journal of Applied Psychology,. 2006;36:1274–1279.

Marwell & Ames, 1979 34.Marwell G, Ames R. Experiments in the provision of public goods: I. Resources, interest, group size and the free rider problem. American Journal of Sociology,. 1979;84:1335–1360. CrossRef

Masclet et al., 2003 35.Masclet D, Noussair C, Tucker S, Villeval M. Monetary and nonmonetary punishment in the voluntary contributions mechanism. American Economic Review,. 2003;93:366–380. CrossRef

Noussair & Tucker, 2005 36.Noussair C, Tucker S. Combining monetary and social sanctions to promote cooperation. Economic Inquiry,. 2005;43:649–660. CrossRef

Oliver, 1980 37.Oliver P. Rewards and punishments as selective incentives for collective action: Theoretical investigations. American Journal of Sociology,. 1980;85:1356–1375. CrossRef

Olson, 1965 38.Olson M. The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1965;.

Orbell et al., 1988 39.Orbell J, Dawes RM, Van de Kragt A. Explaining discussion induced cooperation. Journal of Personality and Social Pyschology,. 1988;54:811–819.

Ostrom et al., 1992 40.Ostrom E, Walker J, Gardner R. Covenants with and without a sword: Self-governance is possible. American Political Science Review,. 1992;86:404–417.

Page et al., 2005 41.Page T, Putterman L, Unel B. Voluntary association in public goods experiments: Reciprocity, mimicry and efficiency. Economic Journal,. 2005;115:1032–1053.

Price et al., 2002 42.Price ME, Cosmides L, Tooby J. Punitive sentiment as an anti-free rider psychological device. Evolution and Human Behavior,. 2002;23:203–231.

Pruitt & Kimmel, 1977 43.Pruitt DG, Kimmel MJ. Twenty years of experimental gaming: Critique, synthesis, and suggestions for the future. Annual Review of Psychology,. 1977;28:363–392.

Rapoport, 1987 44.Rapoport A. Research paradigms and expected utility models for the provision of public goods. Psychological Review,. 1987;94:74–83. CrossRef

Sober & Wilson, 1998 45.Sober E, Wilson DS. Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1998;.

Taylor, 1976 46.Taylor M. Anarchy and cooperation. New York: Wiley; 1976;.

Trivers, 1971 47.Trivers R. The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology,. 1971;46:35–57. CrossRef

Walker & Halloran, 2004 48.Walker J, Halloran MA. Rewards and sanctions and the provision of public goods in one-shot settings. Experimental Economics. 2004;7:235–247.

Watabe et al., 1996 49.Watabe M, Terai S, Hayashi N, Yamagishi T. Cooperation in the one-shot prisoner's dilemma based on expectations ofreciprocity. Japanese Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,. 1996;36:183–196.

Yamagishi, 1986 50.Yamagishi T. The provision of a sanctioning system as a public good. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,. 1986;51:110–116. CrossRef

Yamagishi, 1988 51.Yamagishi T. Seriousness of social dilemmas and the provision of a sanctioning system. Social Psychology Quarterly,. 1988;51:32–42. CrossRef

Yamagishi, 1992 52.Yamagishi T. Group size and the provision of a sanctioning system in a social dilemma. In:  W. B. G. Liebrand,  D. M. Messick,  H. Wilke editor. Social dilemma: Theoretical issues and research findings (pp.267–287). Oxford, UK: Pergamon Press; 1992;.

a Graduate School of Letters, Hokkaido University, Sapporo 060-0810, Japan

b The Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, Tokyo 102-8471, Japan

Corresponding author. Tel.: +81 11 706 4157; fax: +81 11 706 3066.

 The research reported in this paper was supported by grants from The Japan Society for the Promotion of Science.

1 One participant in the combined-effect condition thought that only one participant faced the possibility of punishment, and another in the direct-effect condition thought that the other two members also faced the possibility of punishment.

2 We randomly administered punishment with a probability of 20% when a participant in the combined-effect condition failed to contribute the entire endowment of ¥800. No punishment was administered in the no-punishment condition or in the direct-effect condition.

3 When, for example, four participants were involved in a session, two participants N1 and N2 were assigned to the no-punishment condition, and the other two participants D1 and D2 were assigned to the direct-effect condition. For calculating rewards for N1 and N2, either D1 or D2 was randomly selected as a member of their group. For either D1 or D2, the other two members were N1 and N2. Each of the four participants was thus part of a three-person group.

4 Two participants in the combined-effect condition believed that only one of the other two participants faced the possibility of punishment, and one participant in the direct-effect condition believed that another member also faced the possibility of punishment.

5 While punishment of cooperators in this study seems to be rather high, punishment of cooperators by defectors was also substantial (34%) in the study of Falk et al. (2005).

PII: S1090-5138(07)00038-4

doi:10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2007.04.001



2007:12:16